Felici's law: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>LittleWink
m Disambiguated: conductorElectrical conductor
 
en>Addbot
m Bot: Updating 1 interwikilinks per Wikidata d:q3829767 (Report Errors)
Line 1: Line 1:
In [[recursion theory]], '''hyperarithmetic theory''' is a generalization of Turing computability.  It has close connections with definability in [[second-order arithmetic]] and with weak systems of set theory such as [[Kripke–Platek set theory]].  It is an important tool in [[effective descriptive set theory]].


== Hyperarithmetical sets ==


Tiffany blå nike gratis. Dame Nike Free run nike gratis tropisk twist nike free pink nike free mintgrøn nike Tiffany blå løbesko Nike Free tropisk twist nike free womens billige nike free nike tropisk twist nike gratis. + Dame løbesko Sort, nike free Tiffany blå.<br><br>you'e gjort alt din forskning på Nike Free neon pink.tropical twist mintgrøn Nike løbesko Tiffany blå Nike Free kørsler til salg Dame Nike Free run nike free womens mintgrøn nike free womens tropisk twist nike frit løb. nike free all black Shop Champs Sports for det bedste udvalg af nike free alle sorte sko. silhuet med denne urbane orangelaser appelsin colorway.<br><br>med stor cash flow allerede på plads Continue Reading virkelige eksempler Hvad jeg fik fra Scotts Academy Scotts systemer med på forhånd lavet formularer giver dig mulighed for at omgå 'reinenting Hammer', spilde tid, eller lave masser af fejl Continue Reading virkelige eksempler, jeg kan lide Scotts Programs Efter flere år med at have tilbragt eery weekend og mange eenings remodeling enfamiliehuse at udleje eller sælge, Continue Reading virkelige eksempler Om Scotts Home Study Course Vi købte Scotts hjem undersøgelse kursus og deltog i self storage boot camp i Las Vegas i januar i år.<br><br>tropisk twist nike gratis forsendelse begge veje på tropisk twist Nike, fra vores ast udvalg af stilarter. Tiffany blå Nike Free kørsler til salg Shop Champs Sports for det bedste udvalg af Tiffany blå Nike Free kørsler til salg sko. nike free pink nike free pink Run + Shield Herre løbesko.<br><br>nike gratis varm punch nike gratis varm punch er en sko, der gør det muligt for musklerne i foden at vinde styrke ved proiding mindre konstriktion, er løbere adised til gradvist at bryde ind billig nike free Velkommen til vores online shopping butik NikeFreePlus. nike free koral Vi vil gerne vise dig en beskrivelse her, men hjemmesiden vil ikke tillade os.<br><br>off Nike Free Run Herre Midnight Fog Volt Blå Glow. mere info Kvinder Nike Air Presto trænere PinkAU.off Ray Ban RB Solbriller Arista Frame Wine Red Gradient Lens. tropisk twist nike free tropisk twist Nike Free Run Kvinder Running Sko Wolf GreyPink arken Grå Hvid.<br><br>hakuna jambo Jinsi utata cheo Watu Nike Bure kukimbia iatu, lakini mapato ya ambayo ni Hakika maarufu, hakuna Shaka \\ r \\ rkubuni Kwanza ni Nike Air Max transport mchakato wa kaburi ni ngumu sana, gari anaweza tu kuwa wazi Kwa mlima Mita juu ya usawa wa Bahari ukiukaji Nike Bure mistanke wa masuala ya faragha bruger wamekuwa wazi,<br><br>Reseller Hosting Plans startende fra. mo At Hawk Host er vi dedikeret til proiding vores forhandler hosting kunder med pålidelig og overkommelig forhandler web hosting. DK ISK Space Gigabytes af Transfer Support WHMCS \u0026 SSL-certifikater Inkluderer Fantastico Setup Gebyr:. Nike Free Run + Nike Free Powerlines + II Nike Free.<br><br>Tiffany blå Nike Free Run Vi vil gerne vise dig en beskrivelse her, men hjemmesiden vil ikke tillade os. Nike Free run tropisk twist Run er en anden Nike løbesko løsning for peop. Shop for nike free Tiffany blå Run løbesko og uddannelse sho. billige nike free Shop Champs Sports for det bedste udvalg af billige nike free sko.<br><br>og statslige love og regler kan der være seeral lån, der aren nemt soled gennem overførsel af finansielle lån. Nike Free sko rød sort og hvid er ikke bundet, homoseksuelle atleter, sport er næsten fælles tiltrækning,<br><br>Nike Free run koral Run er en anden Nike løbesko løsning for folk til formål at gøre peo.womens Tiffany blå sko nike free.tropical twist nike free neon pink Dame Nike Free Tiffany blå nike tropisk twist nike gratis mintgrøn nike Tiffany blå hvor kan jeg få Tiffany blå Nike Dame Nike Free run Tiffany blå nike.tiffany blå butik kan støt levere billige nike free.<br><br>Hurtig deliery, og virkelig person serice med et smil. nike free womens mintgrøn Velkommen til vores online shopping butik NikeFreePlus.tropical twist nike free Tiffany blå Tiffany blå nike sko Nike Free.<br><br>koral nike free Velkommen til vores online shopping butik NikeFreePlus. Tiffany blå Nike womens Shop Champs Sports for det bedste udvalg af Tiffany blå Nike damesko. Mere information om Tiffany gratis kørsler sko deriblandt udgivelsesdatoer, priser,<br><br>Alle Nike sko er med den bedste kvalitet og mest up to date design.Lie Stærke Mens \u0026 Womens Black Royal Blå. Få hjælp Kontakt os Forsendelse \u0026 Return Priacy Notice SE MERE orers Indkøbskurv Kassen Min Konto OIN Hvordan bliver Nike medlem og få frynsegoder som gratis forsendelse og kun for medlemmer tilbyde. Nike Free Run sko kan tilpasses layout stærkt efterligner den organiske actiity inden din fod.<br><br>Tiffany blå tropisk twist nike free nike gratis. oin nu og komme væk fra et fremtidigt køb. womens Tiffany blå sko på sale.tropical twist Tiffany blå Nike frit løb nike gratis koral tropisk twist nike free nike gratis.<br><br>Brug sync blitz kan også bidrage til at gøre exclusie fotos. Start din ery egen have kompost stakken. Det fungerer virkelig bedre, og det er mindre expensie end professionelle gødning. Dit rige kompost stak burde være placeret på et sted, der er helt sikkert væk fra direkte sollys og besidder god vandgennemstrømning.<br><br>When you loved this information along with you desire to be given more info relating to [http://youmob.com/mob.aspx?cookietest=true&mob=http%3a%2f%2fwww.lsplaza.com nike shox] kindly stop by our own webpage.
The central focus of hyperarithmetic theory is the sets of [[natural number]]s known as '''hyperarithmetic sets'''. There are three equivalent ways of defining this class of sets; the study of the relationships between these different definitions is one motivation for the study of hyperarithmetical theory.
 
=== Hyperarithmetical sets and definability ===
 
The first definition of the hyperarithmetic sets uses the [[analytical hierarchy]].  
A set of natural numbers is classified at level <math>\Sigma^1_1</math> of this hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of [[second-order arithmetic]] with only existential set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is classified at level <math>\Pi^1_1</math> of the analytical hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second-order arithmetic with only universal set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is <math>\Delta^1_1</math> if it is both <math>\Sigma^1_1</math> and <math>\Pi^1_1</math>. The hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the <math>\Delta^1_1</math> sets.
 
=== Hyperarithmetical sets and iterated Turing jumps: the hyperarithmetical hierarchy ===
 
The definition of hyperarithmetical sets as <math>\Delta^1_1</math> does not directly depend on computability results.  A second, equivalent, definition shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be defined using infinitely iterated [[Turing jump]]s.  This second definition also shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be classified into a hierarchy extending the [[arithmetical hierarchy]]; the hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the sets that are assigned a rank in this hierarchy.
 
Each level of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy corresponds to a countable [[ordinal number]] (ordinal), but not all countable ordinals correspond to a level of the hierarchy. The ordinals used by the hierarchy are those with an '''[[ordinal notation]]''', which is a concrete, effective description of the ordinal.
 
An ordinal notation is an effective description of a countable ordinal by a natural number. A system of ordinal notations is required in order to define the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. The fundamental property an ordinal notation must have is that it describes the ordinal in terms of small ordinals in an effective way. The following inductive definition is typical; it uses a [[pairing function]] <math>\langle \cdot , \cdot\rangle</math>.
* The number 0 is a notation for the ordinal 0.
* If ''n'' is a notation for an ordinal &lambda; then <math>\langle 1, n \rangle</math> is a notation for &lambda; + 1;
* Suppose that &delta; is a limit ordinal. A notation for &delta; is a number of the form <math>\langle 2, e\rangle</math>, where ''e'' is the index of a total computable function <math>\phi_e</math> such that for each ''n'', <math>\phi_e(n)</math> is a notation for an ordinal &lambda;<sub>n</sub> less than &delta; and &delta; is the [[supremum|sup]] of the set <math>\{ \lambda_n \mid n \in \mathbb{N}\}</math>.
 
There are only countably many ordinal notations, since each notation is a natural number; thus there is a countable ordinal which is the supremum of all ordinals that have a notation. This ordinal is known as the [[Large_countable_ordinal#The_Church–Kleene_ordinal|Church-Kleene ordinal]] and is denoted <math>\omega^{CK}_1</math>. Note that this ordinal is still countable, the symbol being only an analogy with the first uncountable ordinal, <math>\omega_{1}</math>. The set of all natural numbers that are ordinal notations is denoted <math>\mathcal{O}</math> and called ''Kleene's <math>\mathcal{O}</math>''.
 
Ordinal notations are used to define iterated Turing jumps. These are sets of natural numbers denoted <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> for each <math>\delta < \omega^{CK}_1</math>. Suppose that &delta; has notation ''e''. The set <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> is defined using ''e'' as follows.
* If &delta; = 0 then <math>0^{(\delta)}= 0</math> is the empty set.
* If &delta; = &lambda; + 1 then <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> is the Turing jump of <math>0^{(\lambda)}</math>. The notations <math>0'</math> and <math>0''</math> are commonly used for <math>0^{(1)}</math> and <math>0^{(2)}</math>, respectively.
* If &delta; is a limit ordinal, let <math>\langle \lambda_n \mid n \in \mathbb{N}\rangle</math> be the sequence of ordinals less than &delta; given by the notation ''e''. The set <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> is given by the rule <math>0^{(\delta)} = \{ \langle n,i\rangle \mid i \in 0^{(\lambda_n)}\}</math>. This is the [[effective join]] of the sets <math>0^{(\lambda_n)}</math>.
Although the construction of <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> depends on having a fixed notation for &delta;, and each infinite ordinal has many notations, a theorem of Spector shows that the [[Turing degree]] of <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> depends only on &delta;, not on the particular notation used, and thus <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> is well defined up to Turing degree.
 
The hyperarithmetical hierarchy is defined from these iterated Turing jumps. A set ''X'' of natural numbers is classified at level &delta; of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, for <math>\delta < \omega^{CK}_1</math>, if ''X'' is [[Turing reduction|Turing reducible]] to <math>0^{(\delta)}</math>. There will always be a least such &delta; if there is any; it is this least &delta; that measures the level of uncomputability of ''X''.
 
=== Hyperarithmetical sets and recursion in higher types ===
 
A third characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets, due to Kleene, uses [[type theory|higher-type]] computable functionals. The type-2 functional <math>{}^2E\colon \mathbb{N}^{\mathbb{N}} \to \mathbb{N}</math> is defined by the following rules:
:<math>{}^2E(f) = 1 \quad</math> if there is an ''i'' such that ''f''(''i'') > 0,
:<math>{}^2E(f) = 0 \quad</math> if there is no ''i'' such that ''f''(''i'') > 0.
Using a precise definition of computability relative to a type-2 functional, Kleene showed that a set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is computable relative to <math>{}^2E</math>.
 
== Example: the truth set of arithmetic ==
 
Every [[arithmetical set]] is hyperarithmetical, but there are many other hyperarithmetical sets. One example of a hyperarithmetical, nonarithmetical set is the set ''T'' of Gödel numbers of formulas of [[Peano axioms|Peano arithmetic]] that are true in the standard natural numbers <math>\mathbb{N}</math>. The set ''T'' is [[Turing reduction|Turing equivalent]] to the set <math>0^{(\omega)}</math>, and so is not high in the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, although it is not arithmetically definable by [[Tarski's indefinability theorem]].
 
== Fundamental results ==
 
The fundamental results of hyperarithmetic theory show that the three definitions above define the same collection of sets of natural numbers. These equivalences are due to Kleene.
 
Completeness results are also fundamental to the theory. A set of natural numbers is '''<math>\Pi^1_1</math> complete''' if it is at level <math>\Pi^1_1</math> of the [[analytical hierarchy]] and every <math>\Pi^1_1</math> set of natural numbers is [[many-one reduction|many-one reducible]] to it. The definition of a <math>\Pi^1_1</math> complete subset of Baire space (<math>\mathbb{N}^\mathbb{N}</math>) is similar.  Several sets associated with hyperarithmetic theory are <math>\Pi^1_1</math> complete:
* Kleene's <math>\mathcal{O}</math>, the set of natural numbers that are notations for ordinal numbers
* The set of natural numbers ''e'' such that the computable function <math>\phi_e(x,y)</math> computes the characteristic function of a well ordering of the natural numbers. These are the indices of [[recursive ordinal]]s.
* The set of elements of Baire space that are the characteristic functions of a well ordering of the natural numbers (using an effective isomorphism <math>\mathbb{N}^\mathbb{N} \cong \mathbb{N}^{\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{N}})</math>.
 
Results known as '''<math>\Sigma^1_1</math> bounding''' follow from these completeness results. For any <math>\Sigma^1_1</math> set ''S'' of ordinal notations, there is an <math>\alpha < \omega^{CK}_1</math> such that every element of ''S'' is a notation for an ordinal less than <math>\alpha</math>. For any subset ''T'' of Baire space consisting only of characteristic functions of well orderings, there is an <math>\alpha < \omega^{CK}_1</math> such that each ordinal represented in ''T'' is less than <math>\alpha</math>.
 
== Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees ==
 
The definition of <math>\mathcal{O}</math> can be relativized to a set ''X'' of natural numbers: in the definition of an ordinal notation, the clause for limit ordinals is changed so that the computable enumeration of a sequence of ordinal notations is allowed to use ''X'' as an oracle. The set of numbers that are ordinal notations relative to ''X'' is denoted <math>\mathcal{O}^X</math>. The supremum of ordinals represented in <math>\mathcal{O}^X</math> is denoted <math>\omega^{X}_1</math>; this is a countable ordinal no smaller than <math>\omega^{CK}_1</math>.
 
The definition of <math>0^{(\delta)}</math> can also be relativized to an arbitrary set <math>X</math> of natural numbers. The only change in the definition is that <math>X^{(0)}</math> is defined to be ''X'' rather than the empty set, so that <math>X^{(1)} = X'</math> is the Turing jump of ''X'', and so on. Rather than terminating at <math>\omega^{CK}_1</math> the hierarchy relative to ''X'' runs through all ordinals less than <math>\omega^{X}_1</math>.
 
The relativized hyperarithmetical hierarchy is used to define '''hyperarithmetical reducibility'''. Given sets ''X'' and ''Y'', we say <math> X \leq_{HYP} Y</math> if and only if there is a <math>\delta < \omega^Y_1</math> such that ''X'' is Turing reducible to <math>Y^{(\delta)}</math>. If <math> X \leq_{HYP} Y</math> and <math> Y \leq_{HYP} X</math> then the notation <math> X \equiv_{HYP} Y</math> is used to indicate ''X'' and ''Y'' are '''hyperarithmetically equivalent'''. This is a coarser equivalence relation than [[Turing reduction|Turing equivalence]]; for example, every set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetically equivalent to its [[Turing jump]] but not Turing equivalent to its Turing jump. The equivalence classes of hyperarithmetical equivalence are known as '''hyperdegrees'''.
 
The function that takes a set ''X'' to <math>\mathcal{O}^X</math> is known as the '''hyperjump''' by analogy with the Turing jump. Many properties of the hyperjump and hyperdegrees have been established. In particular, it is known that [[Turing_degree#Post.27s_problem_and_the_priority_method|Post's problem]] for hyperdegrees has a positive answer: for every set ''X''  of natural numbers there is a set ''Y'' of natural numbers such that <math>X <_{HYP} Y <_{HYP} \mathcal{O}^X</math>.
 
== Generalizations ==
 
Hyperarithmetical theory is generalized by [[Alpha recursion theory|&alpha;-recursion theory]], which is the study of definable subsets of [[admissible ordinal]]s. Hyperarithmetical theory is the special case in which &alpha; is <math>\omega^{CK}_1</math>.
 
== References ==
* H. Rogers, Jr., 1967. ''The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability'', second edition 1987, MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-68052-1 (paperback), ISBN 0-07-053522-1
* G Sacks, 1990.  [http://projecteuclid.org/DPubS?service=UI&version=1.0&verb=Display&page=toc&handle=euclid.pl/1235422631 ''Higher Recursion Theory''], Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-19305-7
* S Simpson, 1999. ''Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic'', Springer-Verlag.
* C.J. Ash, [[Julia F. Knight|J.F. Knight]], 2000. ''Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy'', Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-50072-3
 
== External links ==
* [http://math.uic.edu/~marker/math512/dst.pdf Descriptive set theory]. Notes by David Marker, University of Illinois at Chicago. 2002.
* [http://folk.uio.no/dnormann/LogikkII.pdf Mathematical Logic II]. Notes by Dag Normann, The University of Oslo. 2005.
 
[[Category:Computability theory]]
[[Category:Hierarchy]]

Revision as of 21:42, 19 February 2013

In recursion theory, hyperarithmetic theory is a generalization of Turing computability. It has close connections with definability in second-order arithmetic and with weak systems of set theory such as Kripke–Platek set theory. It is an important tool in effective descriptive set theory.

Hyperarithmetical sets

The central focus of hyperarithmetic theory is the sets of natural numbers known as hyperarithmetic sets. There are three equivalent ways of defining this class of sets; the study of the relationships between these different definitions is one motivation for the study of hyperarithmetical theory.

Hyperarithmetical sets and definability

The first definition of the hyperarithmetic sets uses the analytical hierarchy. A set of natural numbers is classified at level of this hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second-order arithmetic with only existential set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is classified at level of the analytical hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second-order arithmetic with only universal set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is if it is both and . The hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the sets.

Hyperarithmetical sets and iterated Turing jumps: the hyperarithmetical hierarchy

The definition of hyperarithmetical sets as does not directly depend on computability results. A second, equivalent, definition shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be defined using infinitely iterated Turing jumps. This second definition also shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be classified into a hierarchy extending the arithmetical hierarchy; the hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the sets that are assigned a rank in this hierarchy.

Each level of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy corresponds to a countable ordinal number (ordinal), but not all countable ordinals correspond to a level of the hierarchy. The ordinals used by the hierarchy are those with an ordinal notation, which is a concrete, effective description of the ordinal.

An ordinal notation is an effective description of a countable ordinal by a natural number. A system of ordinal notations is required in order to define the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. The fundamental property an ordinal notation must have is that it describes the ordinal in terms of small ordinals in an effective way. The following inductive definition is typical; it uses a pairing function .

There are only countably many ordinal notations, since each notation is a natural number; thus there is a countable ordinal which is the supremum of all ordinals that have a notation. This ordinal is known as the Church-Kleene ordinal and is denoted . Note that this ordinal is still countable, the symbol being only an analogy with the first uncountable ordinal, . The set of all natural numbers that are ordinal notations is denoted and called Kleene's .

Ordinal notations are used to define iterated Turing jumps. These are sets of natural numbers denoted for each . Suppose that δ has notation e. The set is defined using e as follows.

Although the construction of depends on having a fixed notation for δ, and each infinite ordinal has many notations, a theorem of Spector shows that the Turing degree of depends only on δ, not on the particular notation used, and thus is well defined up to Turing degree.

The hyperarithmetical hierarchy is defined from these iterated Turing jumps. A set X of natural numbers is classified at level δ of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, for , if X is Turing reducible to . There will always be a least such δ if there is any; it is this least δ that measures the level of uncomputability of X.

Hyperarithmetical sets and recursion in higher types

A third characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets, due to Kleene, uses higher-type computable functionals. The type-2 functional is defined by the following rules:

if there is an i such that f(i) > 0,
if there is no i such that f(i) > 0.

Using a precise definition of computability relative to a type-2 functional, Kleene showed that a set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is computable relative to .

Example: the truth set of arithmetic

Every arithmetical set is hyperarithmetical, but there are many other hyperarithmetical sets. One example of a hyperarithmetical, nonarithmetical set is the set T of Gödel numbers of formulas of Peano arithmetic that are true in the standard natural numbers . The set T is Turing equivalent to the set , and so is not high in the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, although it is not arithmetically definable by Tarski's indefinability theorem.

Fundamental results

The fundamental results of hyperarithmetic theory show that the three definitions above define the same collection of sets of natural numbers. These equivalences are due to Kleene.

Completeness results are also fundamental to the theory. A set of natural numbers is complete if it is at level of the analytical hierarchy and every set of natural numbers is many-one reducible to it. The definition of a complete subset of Baire space () is similar. Several sets associated with hyperarithmetic theory are complete:

Results known as bounding follow from these completeness results. For any set S of ordinal notations, there is an such that every element of S is a notation for an ordinal less than . For any subset T of Baire space consisting only of characteristic functions of well orderings, there is an such that each ordinal represented in T is less than .

Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees

The definition of can be relativized to a set X of natural numbers: in the definition of an ordinal notation, the clause for limit ordinals is changed so that the computable enumeration of a sequence of ordinal notations is allowed to use X as an oracle. The set of numbers that are ordinal notations relative to X is denoted . The supremum of ordinals represented in is denoted ; this is a countable ordinal no smaller than .

The definition of can also be relativized to an arbitrary set of natural numbers. The only change in the definition is that is defined to be X rather than the empty set, so that is the Turing jump of X, and so on. Rather than terminating at the hierarchy relative to X runs through all ordinals less than .

The relativized hyperarithmetical hierarchy is used to define hyperarithmetical reducibility. Given sets X and Y, we say if and only if there is a such that X is Turing reducible to . If and then the notation is used to indicate X and Y are hyperarithmetically equivalent. This is a coarser equivalence relation than Turing equivalence; for example, every set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetically equivalent to its Turing jump but not Turing equivalent to its Turing jump. The equivalence classes of hyperarithmetical equivalence are known as hyperdegrees.

The function that takes a set X to is known as the hyperjump by analogy with the Turing jump. Many properties of the hyperjump and hyperdegrees have been established. In particular, it is known that Post's problem for hyperdegrees has a positive answer: for every set X of natural numbers there is a set Y of natural numbers such that .

Generalizations

Hyperarithmetical theory is generalized by α-recursion theory, which is the study of definable subsets of admissible ordinals. Hyperarithmetical theory is the special case in which α is .

References

  • H. Rogers, Jr., 1967. The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, second edition 1987, MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-68052-1 (paperback), ISBN 0-07-053522-1
  • G Sacks, 1990. Higher Recursion Theory, Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-19305-7
  • S Simpson, 1999. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, Springer-Verlag.
  • C.J. Ash, J.F. Knight, 2000. Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy, Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-50072-3

External links